Fitch's_paradox_of_knowability

Fitch's paradox of knowability

Fitch's paradox of knowability

Add article description


Fitch's paradox of knowability is one of the fundamental puzzles of epistemic logic. It provides a challenge to the knowability thesis, which states that every truth is, in principle, knowable. The paradox is that this assumption implies the omniscience principle, which asserts that every truth is known. Essentially, Fitch's paradox asserts that the existence of an unknown truth is unknowable. So if all truths were knowable, it would follow that all truths are in fact known.

The paradox is of concern for verificationist or anti-realist accounts of truth, for which the knowability thesis is very plausible,[1] but the omniscience principle is very implausible.

The paradox appeared as a minor theorem in a 1963 paper by Frederic Fitch, "A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts". Other than the knowability thesis, his proof makes only modest assumptions on the modal nature of knowledge and of possibility. He also generalised the proof to different modalities. It resurfaced in 1979 when W. D. Hart wrote that Fitch's proof was an "unjustly neglected logical gem".

Proof

Suppose p is a sentence that is an unknown truth; that is, the sentence p is true, but it is not known that p is true. In such a case, the sentence "the sentence p is an unknown truth" is true; and, if all truths are knowable, it should be possible to know that "p is an unknown truth". But this isn't possible, because as soon as we know "p is an unknown truth", we know that p is true, rendering p no longer an unknown truth, so the statement "p is an unknown truth" becomes a falsity. Hence, the statement "p is an unknown truth" cannot be both known and true at the same time. Therefore, if all truths are knowable, the set of "all truths" must not include any of the form "something is an unknown truth"; thus there must be no unknown truths, and thus all truths must be known.

This can be formalised with modal logic. K and L will stand for known and possible, respectively. Thus LK means possibly known, in other words, knowable. The modality rules used are:

(A) Kpp– knowledge implies truth.
(B)K(p & q) → (Kp & Kq)– knowing a conjunction implies knowing each conjunct.
(C)pLKp– all truths are knowable.
(D)from ¬p, deduce ¬Lp– if p can be proven false without assumptions, then p is impossible (which is equivalent to the rule of necessitation: if q=¬p can be proven true without assumptions (a tautology), then q is necessarily true, therefore p is impossible).

The proof proceeds:

1. Suppose K(p & ¬Kp)
2. Kp & K¬Kpfrom line 1 by rule (B)
3. Kpfrom line 2 by conjunction elimination
4. K¬Kpfrom line 2 by conjunction elimination
5. ¬Kpfrom line 4 by rule (A)
6. ¬K(p & ¬Kp)from lines 3 and 5 by reductio ad absurdum, discharging assumption 1
7. ¬LK(p & ¬Kp)from line 6 by rule (D)
8. Suppose p & ¬Kp
9. LK(p & ¬Kp)from line 8 by rule (C)
10. ¬(p & ¬Kp)from lines 7 and 9 by reductio ad absurdum, discharging assumption 8.
11. pKpfrom line 10 by a classical tautology about the material conditional (negated conditionals)

The last line states that if p is true then it is known. Since nothing else about p was assumed, it means that every truth is known.

Since the above proof uses minimal assumptions about the nature of L, replacing L with F (see Prior's tense logic (TL)) provides the proof for "If all truth can be known in the future, then they are already known right now".

Generalisations

The proof uses minimal assumptions about the nature of K and L, so other modalities can be substituted for "known". Joe Salerno gives the example of "caused by God": rule (C) becomes that every true fact could have been caused by God, and the conclusion is that every true fact was caused by God. Rule (A) can also be weakened to include modalities that don't imply truth. For instance instead of "known" we could have the doxastic modality "believed by a rational person" (represented by B). Rule (A) is replaced with:

(E) BpBBp– rational belief is transparent; if p is rationally believed, then it is rationally believed that p is rationally believed.
(F)¬(Bp & B¬p)– rational beliefs are consistent

This time the proof proceeds:

1. Suppose B(p & ¬Bp)
2. Bp & B¬Bpfrom line 1 by rule (B)
3. Bpfrom line 2 by conjunction elimination
4. BBpfrom line 3 by rule (E)
5. B¬Bpfrom line 2 by conjunction elimination
6. BBp & B¬Bpfrom lines 4 and 5 by conjunction introduction
7. ¬(BBp & B¬Bp)by rule (F)
8. ¬B(p & ¬Bp)from lines 6 and 7 by reductio ad absurdum, discharging assumption 1

The last line matches line 6 in the previous proof, and the remainder goes as before. So if any true sentence could possibly be believed by a rational person, then that sentence is believed by one or more rational persons.

Some anti-realists advocate the use of intuitionistic logic; however, except for the last line, which moves from there are no unknown truths to all truths are known, the proof is, in fact, intuitionistically valid.

The knowability thesis

Rule (C) is generally held to be at fault rather than any of the other logical principles employed. It may be contended that this rule does not faithfully translate the idea that all truths are knowable, and that rule (C) should not apply unrestrictedly. Kvanvig contends that this represents an illicit substitution into a modal context.

Gödel's Theorem proves that in any recursively axiomatized system sufficient to derive mathematics (e.g. Peano Arithmetic), there are statements which are undecidable. In that context, it is difficult to state that "all truths are knowable" since some potential truths are uncertain.

However, jettisoning the knowability thesis does not necessarily solve the paradox, since one can substitute a weaker version of the knowability thesis called (C').

(C')x(((x & ¬Kx) & LKx) & LK((x & ¬Kx) & LKx))– There is an unknown, but knowable truth, and it is knowable that it is an unknown, but knowable truth.

The same argument shows that (C') results in contradiction, indicating that any knowable truth is either known, or it is unknowable that it is an unknown yet knowable truth; conversely, it states that if a truth is unknown, then it is unknowable, or it is unknowable that it is knowable yet unknown.

See also


Notes

  1. Müller, Vincent C. W.; Stein, Christian (1996). Epistemic theories of truth: The justifiability paradox investigated. Universidade de Santiago de Compostela. pp. 95–104.

References


Share this article:

This article uses material from the Wikipedia article Fitch's_paradox_of_knowability, and is written by contributors. Text is available under a CC BY-SA 4.0 International License; additional terms may apply. Images, videos and audio are available under their respective licenses.